by J J Cohen
[read Karl on Kadar Koli first]
So I've been working away on my book, making fairly decent progress despite two ongoing family crises and a barrage of other responsibilities.
Below is the draft opening of chapter two, called simply "Radiance," and glossed with the parenthetical "The Force of Stone." After this introductory section I have an explication of Merlin as an ideal or lapidary reader in Geoffrey of Monmouth and Wace, a section on Roger Caillois and the beauty of stone (as well as his theory of objective, universal and inhuman aesthetics) ... and that's the 10K of words I have so far. Next likely comes a movement the subterranean realms mapped by Marie de France in "Yonec" as well as the Breton lay Sir Orfeo.
---------
If physical things are described as firm and
hard, this is clearly the case only for whatever tries to move them. (Graham
Harman, Prince of Networks 143)
miroir d'eau, emptied |
This chapter explores
the radiative power of stone, an inherent and inhuman force that medieval
writers called virtus. Modern English
does not contain an adequate synonym for that powerful Latin word. I will use “aesthetic
power” as a loose translation, though in a modified sense that brings the term aesthetics closer to its Greek root in aisthÄ“ta: “perceptible things,”
that which is sensation-provoking, that which triggers extraordinary and
perhaps unexpected affective and cognitive relation. Art and beauty have been
central to aesthetics since its controversial launching as a science in eighteenth-century
Germany, but mainly as static and inactive phenomena to be discerned, judged
and savored. Stone teaches us that even the most inert and mundane of
substances awaits its “postdisenchanted” reappraisal, revealing itself as temporally
thick, relentlessly active and imagination-provoking.[i] A dynamic prod to action, emotion,
memory and transformative confederation, aesthetic power must be as germane to
things that are repellent or commonplace as to that which is magnificent.[ii] Aesthetics in this formulation
will not be subjective (concerned only with individual or cultural matters of
taste), but object-oriented and disanthropocentric (following the paths and unfolding
the powers of things and materialities themselves). It is a tool for mapping the
radiative power of objects, their ability to connect, effect, impede and
intensify in ways that are not simply historical or local. Such conjunctive and
emissive ability becomes most evident in an interspace, in a meeting of human collaborator
with a rock ready to divulge something of the unexpected exquisiteness of its
surface, the hidden artistry of its depths, its yearning to become monumental.
Yes, yearning. There will be many such
anthropomorphic turns of phrase in this chapter. Their aim is not to suggest
that stone acts just like a human. It
is not my intention to humanize the lithic, as if assimilation were the
necessary prerequisite to a more ethical mode of reading materiality or of
thickening human relations to the nonhuman world. Such a method assumes a
primal rift then builds what could be an environmental justice upon the
presupposition of human dominion, rather than interrogating how that chasm
opened and through what exertions that power has been sustained. Cautiously
anthropomorphic language estranges. The wonder it engenders enables an exploration
of how things -- objects and substances -- sometimes deeply intertwine
themselves in human affairs, sometimes withdraw into unknowability, apathy, or indifference,
but continually intimate that the exceptionality humans grant themselves is more
precarious than patent. This power of things to re-orient the world can be described
as aesthetic. It might also be glossed as radiance. It always precipitates astonishment,
the state of what in Middle English was written astoned. This
ubiquitous adjective derives from the Anglo-Norman French verb estoner, “to stun” or “to be stunned,”
which in turn comes from Latin tonare,
“to thunder.” Astonish is therefore a
word with a sonorous etymology, and indicates the feeling of being outside
oneself that arrives at a sudden thunderclap. Yet for both medieval and modern Anglophone
audiences “astonish” carries a lithic suggestiveness: a-stoned. Thus Chaucer describes a stunned Pandarus, shamed into
silence by Troilus’s rebuke, as follows: “This
Pandarus ... stant, astoned of thise causes tweye, / As stille as ston”
(Troilus and
Criseyde 5.1728-29). Astonished
people routinely fall to the ground, as the examples of astoned compiled by the Middle
English Dictionary reveal. Heidegger’s designation of stones as weltlos (“wordless”) seems to designate
the same state, until we remember that astonishment is a movement, an
oscillation. The astoned person
returns to consciousness – though perhaps, like Saul after the thunderbolt, no
longer quite the same.
Radiance as
wonder-making or becoming astoned designates
a set of relations and qualities that are ineluctably ethical and aesthetic, with
that latter term understood as naming a nonhuman effectivity rather than a culturally
projected quality to be applauded. Radiance is a potentially inconstant but nonetheless
inherent, agentic, and affective force, the collective name for diverse powers possessed
by objects to enable them at times to touch and form alliances with other
bodies and forces. Objects may withdraw completely from contact; contact may be
withdrawn completely from objects. Both this relation-making power and the ability
to recede have profoundly material consequences. Stone becomes at once an
inexhaustible force and an entity the secrets of which can never be fully plumbed,
no matter how many times or how accurately its possibilities are translated
into human terms or assimilated into sustained alliance. Rock thereby opens up
a world of things that cannot be reduced to history, use value, relational
significance, or a substantiality determined only by cultural incorporation. The
lithic possesses an anthropodecentric effect: it reminds that entities subsist
regardless of human relations, independent of perception, and are therefore on
the same ontological plane as both humans and other objects. The philosopher
Graham Harman uses this insight to argue for the integrity and autonomy of all things:
When things
withdraw from presence into their dark subterranean reality, they distance
themselves not only from human beings but from
each other as well. If the human perception of a house or a tree is forever
haunted by some hidden surplus in the things that never becomes present, the
same is true of the sheer causal interaction between rocks or raindrops. Even
inanimate things only unlock each other's realities to a minimal extent,
reducing one another to caricatures ... even if rocks are not sentient
creatures, they never encounter one another in their deepest being, but only as present-at-hand … The true chasm in
ontology lies not between humans and the world, but between objects and relations.[iii]
The material world, that is, can
never be constricted into a merely human frame. Rocks form more relations with nonhumans
than they do with architects, gardeners, and the pavers of roads. Harman’s aim
is to bypass the “weary world/human dualism” not by affirming or overcoming this
supposed rift but, with Bruno Latour, “starting with countless actors rather
than a pre-given duality of two types of
actors,” and thereby shifting “philosophy from its stalemated trench war toward
the richness of things themselves” (Prince
of Networks 119). To the charge of panpsychism or animism that often arrives
when a philosopher speaks of such intentional objects, Harman pointedly replies
“Rather than anthropomorphizing the inanimate realm, I am morphing the human
realm into a variant of the inanimate” (212). He is in surprisingly good
medieval company.
All
rock potentially exerts a relation-making or impeding agency, as anyone who has
ever built a stone wall, attempted boulder climbing, or beachcombed and found
themselves drawn to a particular stone along a shore strewn with smooth stones
knows. Such lithic radiance is the trigger to the geologist Jan Zalasiewicz’s
book The Planet in a Pebble: A Journey
Into Earth’s Deep History. The compacted energy, mass, gravity and time
within a banded fragment of the Welsh shore extends an invitation to
wonderment, enabling Zalasiewicz’s travels into paleogeology, a history in which
landmasses crush against each other and mountains bulge. Zalasiewicz’s pebble
perpetually retains an ability to open stories about a world immeasurably vast,
temporally as well as spatially. The medieval historian Geoffrey of Monmouth
discovered a similar potency in Stonehenge, the rocks of which have moved over
tremendous distances and endure for spans that humans can only with great
difficulty conceive. Of the structure’s megaliths Geoffrey has Merlin declare:
‘Mistici sunt
lapides et ad diuersa medicamenta salubres. Gigantes olim aportauerunt eos ex
ultimis finibus Affricae et posuerunt in Hibernia dum eam inhabitarent. Erat
autem causa ut balnea infra ipsos conficerent cum infirmitate grauarentur.
Lauabant namque lapides et infra balnea diffundebant, unde aegroti curabantur.
Misecebant etiam cum herbarum confectionibus, unde uulnerati sanabantur. Non
est ibu lapis qui medicamento careat.’ (History
of the Kings of Britain 173)
[‘The stones are
magic and can effect various cures. They were brought long ago from the
farthest shores of Africa by giants, who erected them in Ireland while they
lived there. Their purpose was to set up baths among them whenever they were
ill. They used to wash the stones and pour the water into baths to cure
illnesses. They also used to mix in herbal compounds to heal wounds. There is
not a stone among them that does not have some medicinal power.’ 172]
Merlin knows that the stones radiate
power, and that through alliance with them this force can be intensified for
the healing of wounds and the ensuring that the memory of those slain in battle
never fades. This potency is always there, innate to the stone itself, but can
be medicinally harnessed only through a water, herbs and fleshly contact. The
structure’s efficacy can also be glimpsed in its ability to catalyze story, here
engendering a narrative of rocks moving from Africa to Ireland to Britain
through the collaboration of giants, a prophet, ships and men. Stonehenge is
agential, even restorative, but that power is known only through gregarious
alliance.
[i]
“Postdisenchanted” is Carolyn Dinshaw’s term from a roundtable on “Theorizing
Queer Temporalities” (185), put to excellent use by Karl Steel in How to Make a Human 244.
[ii]
Tim Morton makes a similar argument in Ecology
Without Nature.
[iii]
The quotation is from Tool-Being 2.
Kris Coffield composed the Wikipedia entry for “Object-oriented ontology” and
does an excellent job of explicating objects and relations. Compare also this
account by Harman in Prince of Networks:
“Objects are not defined by their relations: instead they are what enter into
relations in the first place, and their allies can never fully mine their ores.
In Heideggerian terms, objects enter relations but withdraw from them as well;
objects are built from components, but exceed those components … An object
stands apart – not just from its manifestations to humans, but possibly from
its own accidents, relations, qualities, moments, or pieces” (132, 152).
2 comments:
Mutt : Ore you astonaged, jute you?
Jute : Oye am thonthorstrok, thing mud.
Finnegans Wake 18
This is gorgeous writing. Is there any way to disentangle the *inhuman* aesthetic power of stone from our ability to perceive that? I see here that you will take the object-oriented route to attempt just such an exploration--will you discuss the *sensual* versus the *real*, a la Harman as well, as one way of approaching the stone-everything else intermesh?
Post a Comment