by CAROLYNN VAN DYKE
[Note from Eileen: Carolynn Van Dyke's post here is a continuation of the ongoing dialogue stemming from papers presented at the session Ruth Evans organized on "The Descriptive Turn" at the biennial meeting of the New Chaucer Society held in Portland a few weeks ago -- Eileen Joy's and Julie Orlemanski's expanded papers already posted HERE and HERE, and Ruth Evans's response to Julie's paper HERE.]
CLOSE BUT NOT CLOSED
The first thing I’ll
say about the descriptive turn is, in brief, “been there, done that.” Many
arguments in the texts that Ruth Evans distributed for this seminar [see Works
Cited, below] resonate with what medievalists have been doing for some time. Heather
Love associates the “turn” with a rejection of
“the ideology of humanism” (“Close But Not Deep”)—a phrase used with
comparable scorn sixty years ago by D. W. Robertson, Jr., Bernard Huppé, and
other exegetical critics. Of course, the Robertsonians might exemplify another of Love’s targets,
the presumption of the critic to “[interpret] divine messages” in acts of
“ethical heroism”—but other Chaucerians slammed into that target long ago. I
refer to critics like Talbot Donaldson and Charles Muscatine, who practiced the
“close but not deep” reading that Love advocates. Repudiating patristic
exegesis, attending instead to manifest features of tone and style, Donaldson
emulated the position that he attributes to Chaucer’s own persona, that of—in
Love’s phrase—“humble analyst and observer.” More recently, medievalists have
anticipated the “descriptivists” in other ways. Few of those who read papers at
NCS idealize a stable “text,” for instance, nor do we “conflat[e] the social
practice of reading with the activity of expert readers,” as John Frow puts it (“On
Midlevel Concepts”). We study communities of readers based on gender, language,
class, sexuality, and ideology, and we are keenly aware of the diversity and
materiality of individual manuscripts. Nor do we generally celebrate what Love
disparages as the “singularity of the literary” (“Forms of Description”). That
is, medievalists seem to spend less time on what she calls “the metaphysical
and humanist concerns of heremeneutics” (Love, “Close But Not Deep”) than on
codicology, natural and social history, and philosophical and theological frameworks.
We often raise concerns that might be called pre- or post-humanist.
Indeed, we are
spending more time on such matters than we once did. And that leads me to a
second and less self-congratulatory point about the descriptive turn. If many
of its attacks leave us unscathed, we might benefit from its fresh and forceful
defense of reading. Particularly exciting to me is Heather Love’s call to redefine
literary studies as “a discipline defined by reading or close reading”—that is,
“reading across fields.” To me, the best recent work in medieval studies reads texts—poems,
encyclopedias, laws, manuals, records—not just closely but continuously, from
beginning to end, with sustained attention.
And with humility.
That word surfaces in several of the essays that Evans distributed, and
humility shapes nearly all of them, especially Latour’s moving reconsideration
of his own participation in critique. Heather Love’s reading of Beloved is avowedly modest: she retreats
from her original confidence (shared by many readers) that the novel’s
climactic moments endorse an ethical stance that she had anticipated and could
expound authoritatively. Similarly, in reading the lyrics of Bernart de
Vendatorn, Simon Gaunt backs off a little from his standpoint as a brilliant
exponent of critical queer studies; moreover, he relinquishes the somewhat
arrogant skepticism of many modern readers toward the troubadours’ religious
and sacrificial discourse.
Equally interesting
about Gaunt’s essay, however, is his employment of psychoanalytic concepts. That
raises my third comment about the descriptive turn. To me, Gaunt seems to read both
“close” and “deep.” On the one hand, he “attends to what is most obvious” about
Bernhart’s lyrics, taking them “at face value”—here I borrow Love’s quotation from Leah Marcus and Stephen Best in Representations. On the other, he also
demonstrates what he calls “functional” parallels not just with religion but
also with Lacan’s analysis of “desire of/for the Other.” This is hardly “flat”
or “thin” reading. Indeed, I would have found Gaunt’s close reading less coherent
without the psychoanalytic parallel (though I seldom find Lacan coherent in
isolation).
The power of
Gaunt’s close-and-deep reading leads to my fourth and final point, which
concerns description itself. Some descriptivists ask that we “reject the
traditional humanist categories of experience, consciousness, depth, and
motivation” (I quote Evans’s paraphrase of François Dosse); but those
categories inform Gaunt’s essay as fully as does his “atten[tion] to what is
most obvious.” And they inform at least one of the fields on which the
descriptive turn bases itself. I refer to animal ethology, the systematic study
of animal behavior. Love writes that ethologists are “less interested in
motivation than in gestures, behavior, and pattern” (“Close,” 378). But Gregory
Bateson, whose work Love cites in this regard, writes about the ways in which
nonhuman primates signal their
motives—in particular, playfulness instead of aggression (Steps to an Ecology of Mind, 179-81). More recently, Marc Bekoff
argues that the behavior of a wolf or baboon can be best described with
reference to affective states and motivations—that is, described more economically
and with more predictive value than it can be in rigidly objective terms (Emotional Lives of Animals, 121). And empirical
work in neurology has shown that to label as “empathy” certain cognitive
responses (in both human and nonhuman animals) is an act not of inference or
interpretation but of accurate description: neural activity in an observer’s
brain mirrors that in the brain of the creature being observed (citations in,
e.g., Bekoff 12 and 128). The brain re-writes what it sees. Indeed, on a
somatic level, empathy is description.
To suggest how
reading might be both descriptive and empathetic, I turn briefly to a text that
has received too little reading of any kind: Robert Henryson’s “Morall
Fabillis.” Work on the fables has focused primarily on the relationship between
what John Marlin calls the “humanism of the [Aesopian] tales” and their
didactic, often incompatible moralitates
(Marlin 135). In the last of the thirteen narratives, a naïve mouse accepts a
toad’s duplicitous offer of help crossing a river. As the two struggle, a kite
snatches and eats them both. As Edward Wheatley writes, Henryson supplies two epimythia,
or “morals”—one “social” (don’t trust false companions) and one spiritual (the body
bears the soul downward until death attacks) (Wheatley, 94-96). Attending to
“what is most obvious,” readers have noted that the morals contradict: the
mouse might have declined the toad’s offer, just as we can avoid false friends,
but the soul can hardly refuse the body’s portage through what Henryson calls
the “watter [that] is the warld” (Henryson, l. 2955). And the second moral jars
against the narrative itself, for mouse and toad were equally corporeal; before
meeting the toad/body, the mouse/soul yearned not for heaven but for easy eating
in a field of grain. Wheatley and others confront the divergence directly: they
conclude that Henryson exposes the “variety inherent in the scholastic fable
tradition,” or places the reader “in the uncertain space between precept and
[narrative] example” (Wheatley 99, Marlin 145). Their conclusions remind me of
John Frow’s account of descriptivisim. Frow’s “midlevel concepts” arise, he
explains, not just from “an aggregation of elements heterogeneously and
contingently assembled at any one moment of the social” but from “the recursive
ordering effects by which the social is assembled (and precariously maintained).”
So too, we can see Henryson’s inconsistent moralitates
as interacting recursively with each other and the narrative to produce
contingent meanings.
But that
formulation is description only at a high level of abstraction. It bypasses elements of the texts
themselves that most readers would call
“description”: narrative and sensory details. In Henryson, those elements take
us inside the characters, who are—I have argued elsewhere—bimorphic. On the one
hand, their animal bodies are vividly detailed and intrinsic to the plot. The
mouse can’t cross the river on her “short shanks”; she mistrusts the toad
because of its wrinkled face and cheeks, its hoarse voice, and its “harsky
hyde”; the kite pulls their skins intact over their heads before eating them,
flesh “and guts also” (2779, 2819-22, 2903-6). Meanwhile, however, the mouse
seems surprised when the toad proposes to get her across the river without a
horse, bridge, or ship, as though she didn’t know that neither of them is
human. Before agreeing to lash herself to the toad, the mouse expresses her mistrust
by citing “clerks” who discern “the inclination of man’s thought . . .
according to the bodily complexion” (2824-29; my emphasis). Presumably no mouse
would refer to a toad as a man, and in any case, no mouse would appeal to
clerkly authority. But what this anthro-mouse says sounds comically apt to both
species. Her nervous discourse translates into human rhetoric the uncertainty
of a small rodent confronting an amphibian that might be a predator. (Large
toads can eat small mice but usually don’t.) Conversely, a human being might
inflate her own autonomic recoil from ugliness as scholarly wisdom.
Close-reading of this passage reveals trans-species subjectivity. The shifting moralizations
do not simply reorder surface-reading; they open it further, enlarging the
descriptive scope. Now the mouse and toad manifest entangled but conflicting
impulses within humans; they are also any two subjects, human or otherwise, who
can be comrades or predator and prey. What remains constant beneath the diverse
forms is the experience common to the animals and readers alike, struggling and
scheming but oblivious to the deadly kite.
In both of her essays provided for this seminar,
Heather Love borrows a phrase from Latour to indicate what we can gain by “a
turn from interpretation to description.” Like Latour’s “constructive”
sociology, she writes, reading that is close but not deep “aims to show ‘what
the real world is really like’” (Love, “Close,” 377 and
388; also “Forms,” 8). Her embrace of that phrase surprises me because she also
laments the “longing for a ‘new reign of Truth’ in our institutional DNA”
(“Close, 388). “The real world” and
(capital-T) “Truth” are not identical, of course, but readers of Langland know
that immersion in one can lead to the search for the other. Fields of folk (or actor/system
networks?), dungeons ruled by Wrong, and towers of Truth are all right there on
the surface, in multiple forms that have to be re-described. That surface is seldom
“flat” or “thin.” Thus our descriptions must be close but not closed, always open
to depth.
Works Cited
Frow, John. "On Midlevel Concepts." New
Literary History 41.2 (2010): 237-252. Project MUSE. Web.*
Gaunt,
Simon. “A Martyr to Love: Sacrificial Desire in the Poetry of Bernart de
Ventadorn,” Journal of Medieval and Early
Modern Studies 31 (2001): 477-506.*
Goldstein, R. James. “Writing in Scotland, 1058-1560.” The Cambridge History of Medieval English
Literature, ed. David Wallace (Cambridge: Cambridge U P, 1999), p. 240
[229-54].
Henryson, Robert. Poems.
Clarendon Medieval and Tudor Series. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963.
Love, Heather. “Close but not
Deep: Literary Ethics and the Descriptive Turn.” New Literary History, 2010, 41: 371–391.*
_____. “Forms of Description:
Reading Across the Humanities and the Social Sciences.” Unpublished lecture tdelivered
March 10, 2011, UC-Berkeley. *
Marlin, John. “Robert
Henryson's 'Morall Fabilles': Irony, Allegory, and Humanism in Late-Medieval
Fables.” Fifteenth-Century Studies 34
(2009): 133-147.
Wheatley, Edward. “Scholastic
Commentary and Robert Henryson's Morall Fabillis: The Aesopic Fables.” Studies in Philology 91 (1994): 70-99.
*Essays distributed by Ruth
Evans for consideration for the seminar.
are we as much plumbing/excavating depths as adding layers, cutting and pasting collages, and is there not a sense in which we are not so much describing but prescribing, suggesting new angles of approach, trumpeting new aspects dawning?
ReplyDelete-dmf
http://www.npr.org/blogs/13.7/2012/02/03/146332808/seeing-what-you-mean?sc=tw&cc=share